Show simple item record

dc.contributor.authorHutto, D.
dc.date.accessioned2007-09-03T09:16:27Z
dc.date.available2007-09-03T09:16:27Z
dc.date.issued2006
dc.identifier.citationHutto , D 2006 , ' Turning hard problems on their heads ' , Phenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences , vol. 5 , no. 1 , pp. 75-88 . https://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-9013-8
dc.identifier.issn1568-7759
dc.identifier.otherPURE: 186084
dc.identifier.otherPURE UUID: 8e2397da-9581-4b0f-af06-34a195b1b456
dc.identifier.otherdspace: 2299/534
dc.identifier.otherScopus: 33745635869
dc.identifier.urihttp://hdl.handle.net/2299/534
dc.descriptionThe original publication is available at www.springerlink.com Copyright Springer
dc.description.abstractMuch of the difficulty in assessing theories of consciousness stems from their advocates not supplying adequate or convincing characterisations of the phenomenon (or data) they hope to explain. Yet, to make any reasonable assessment this is precisely what is required, for it is not as if our ‘pre-theoretical’ intuitions are philosophically innocent. In what follows, I will attempt to reveal, using a recent debate between Chalmers and Dennett as a foil, why, in approaching this topic, we cannot characterise the data purely first-personally or third-personally nor, concomitantly, can we start such investigations using either first-personal or third-personal methods.en
dc.language.isoeng
dc.relation.ispartofPhenomenology and the Cognitive Sciences
dc.titleTurning hard problems on their headsen
dc.contributor.institutionPhilosophy
dc.description.statusPeer reviewed
rioxxterms.versionofrecordhttps://doi.org/10.1007/s11097-005-9013-8
rioxxterms.typeJournal Article/Review
herts.preservation.rarelyaccessedtrue


Files in this item

Thumbnail

This item appears in the following Collection(s)

Show simple item record